Greek -ízo Derivatives: A Conceptual Analysis *

Chariton Charitonidis (Cologne)


 

1 Introduction

This paper addresses some aspects of -ízo derivation in Modern Greek using the model of conceptual structures by Jackendoff (1983, 1990, 1992), whereby special attention is paid to the semantic under-determination of word-formation rules. For the analysis, 182 -ízo derivatives with a monomorphemic/simple base were considered (see appendix 1).1 These were extracted from a total of 3506 -ízo verbs from the online version of the 'Reverse Index of Modern Greek' (Anastasiádhi-Simeonídhi 2002).2 The selected 182 verbs had to conform to the embedding of the content of the base into a minimal conceptual structure and to appear inside a group of alternation classes (see below). Verbs with an irregular semantic connection to their base were not considered (the members of this category can be thought of as products of once-only-rules, approximately). Strong metaphorical and literary uses were also excluded.3 Note that only NPi __ NP and NP __ frames are addressed in this paper, whereby an ízo derivative appears as a causative active a variant or as a non-causative active/non-active b variant, respectively.4


2 Conceptual constituents and semantic fields

Jackendoff (1990: 22) argues that 'the essential units of conceptual structure are conceptual constituents, each of which belongs to one of a small set of major ontological categories... such as Thing, Event, State, Action, Place, Path, Property, and Amount.' 5

These conceptual constituents define an argument structure at the conceptual level which is not identical to the syntactic argument structure. The former consists of conceptual constituents which completely define the content of a lexical unit in relation to cross-classifying semantic fields in conceptual structure (see below), whereas the latter refers to 'what makes a lexical head induce argument positions in syntactic structure' (LL).

This means, for example, that in a sentence like (1) the conceptual structure contains one Event with three arguments in the spatial field, i.e. the Things [JÓRGOS] 6 (agent), [FAÍ] (reference object), and [ALÁTI] (theme), represented by the base of alatízi, whereas the argument structure in syntax contains the predicate alatízi with two arguments, i.e. to faí (theme) and o Jórgos (agent).

(1) Ο Γιώργος αλατίζει το φαΐ.
O Jórgos alatízi to faí.
the Jórgos he.salts the meal
'Jórgos salts/is salting the meal.'

-ízo derivatives show the following correspondence between (some of) the conceptual (or ontological) categories above and the lexical category of the base:

A Noun can express a Thing (see aláti in alatízo), an Event (see laxtára in laxtarízo), an Action (see zóri in zorízo), a Place (see alóni in alonízo), and a Property (see sosialismós or sosialistikós in sosialízo). An Adjective can only express a Property (see prásinos in prasinízo1) and finally, an Adverb can express an Event (see xarámi in xaramízo) or a Place (see adíkri in adikrízo).

Before we proceed, two important issues must be mentioned. The first is the reference of the base. According to the Referentiality Principle, all phrases that express [TOKEN] conceptual constituents in the spatial field are referential unless there is a linguistic marking to the contrary (Jackendoff 1983: 94). If we extend this principle to verb morphology, the conceptual content of the base of a derivative is considered as referential, provided that it is embedded in a conceptual structure in the spatial field independent of external (syntactic) factors. Such factors would prescribe, for example, that the presence of an article is indispensable to settling the reference for a noun in Modern Greek. A linguistic marking that the conceptual content of the base is not referential may be, for example, the existence of a phrase in syntax with the same indexing (see rule of Argument Fusion in section 1.3).

The second issue is the conceptual category of the base. As Sasse (1993: 204) states, a list of ontological categories does not warrant the complete differentiation of the content of lexical units since the same unit can be thought of as an instantiation of another category of the same set, e.g. a Thing can be considered as Property. In my view, the embedding of the content of the base in a conceptual structure (e.g. as theme or goal) related to narrow and extended semantic fields (see below) can, for the most part, account for these ambiguous considerations, explaining how different verb readings are produced (see various ambiguous structures in section 1.4). I don't mean that the task of defining the conceptual category of the base is always easy, cf. the derivative onidhízo whose base ónidhos can be considered to denote an Event or a State. In cases like this, I have favoured an interpretation which conforms to the structural position of the conceptual constituent and the overall attested patterns (see section 1.4).

The fixing of the above correspondence between lexical and ontological categories connected with minimal lexical decomposition (see the next sections) has major consequences for a thematic relations approach.

To understand this, let us first look at a well-known formulation of such an approach, i.e. the Thematic Relations Hypothesis by Jackendoff7:

(2) Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH)
In any semantic field of [EVENTS] and [STATES], the principal event-, state-, path-, and place-functions are a subset of those used for the analysis of spatial location and motion. Fields differ in only three possible ways:
a. what sorts of entities may appear as theme;
b. what sorts of entities may appear as reference objects;
c. what kind of relation assumes the role played by location in the field of spatial expressions.
(Jackendoff, Semantics and Cognition 1983:188)

In the following, five cross-classifying semantic fields are presented, i.e. the fields of spatial, temporal, possessive, identificational, and circumstantial. For these, I sometimes use the term narrow semantic fields in order to distinguish them from the extended semantic fields or simply semantic fields (introduced by the author and indicated with capital letters) which are related to the situational context of the Event. 8

1. The following sentence exemplifies an Event in the spatial field:

(3) Αλατίζει το φαΐ.
Alatízi to faí.
he.salts the meal
'He salts the meal.'

The theme in the above sentence is the Thing [ALÁTI], represented by aláti, the base of alatízo. It moves to another Thing, i.e. the reference object [FAÍ] 'meal,' which represents the role of location. In an alternations approach, where it is assumed that lexical units are primarily stored on the basis of the participation of an agent in coherent recurrent Events, 9 the spatial field must be further specified, namely it has to be extended to the semantic field SUBSTANCE, which is the super-category of the entity denoted by the base and perhaps in addition to COOKING.

2. According to the Thematic Relations Hypothesis in the temporal field, Events and States appear as theme, Times appear as reference object, and Time of occurrence represents the role of location (Jackendoff 1983: 189), cf. the following sentence:

(4) Οι συνομιλίες τερμάτισαν/ τερματίστηκαν.
I sinomilíes termátisan/termatístikan.
the talks ended/were ended
'The talks ended.'

In (4), the Event [SINOMILÍES], represented by the subject-NP i sinomilíes 'the talks,' appears as theme and the time Event [TÉRMA], the content of the verb base térma 'end,' appears as the reference object and represents the role of location (in other words, 'the talks came to an end'). Likewise, in an alternations approach the temporal field to which the verb termatízo belongs, must be further specified as TIME & END according to the content of the base.

3. In the possessive field, Things appear as theme, Things appear as reference object, and being alienably possessed plays the role of location 10 (Jackendoff 1983: 192), e.g. in (5) [KÉRDHOS], the content of the verb base, appears as Theme and [MARÍA] appears as reference object, simultaneously playing the role of location (in other words 'the gain went to María').

(5) Η Μαρία κέρδισε ένα αυτοκίνητο.
I María kérdhise éna aftikínito.
the Marí she.won one car
'Mary won a car.'

We do not have to assume a different extended field in order to accommodate the semantics of the Thing denoted by the base, since kérdhos 'gain' denotes possession anyway (for the fusion of the contents of kérdhos and aftokínito see the rule of Argument Fusion in section 1.3).

4. The identificational semantic field appears often among the examined -ízo derivatives: it is closely related to Events of change of state or ascription of properties. In the latter case, an adjective usually appears as the base of the derivative. In this field Things appear as theme, Thing types and Properties appear as reference objects, and being an instance of a category or having a property plays the role of location (Jackendoff 1983: 194), 11 cf. the following sentence:

(6) Ο ουρανός κοκκίνισε.
O uranós kokínise.
the sky it.reddend
'The sky reddend.'

In (6) uranós 'sky' represents the theme [URANÓS] and adjective kókinos 'red,' the base of the verb kokínise, represents the entity [KÓKINOS], which plays the role of location (in other words 'the sky turned red'). So that the verb can be embedded in a situational frame, the semantic field must be further specified as COLOUR denoting the super-category of the Property denoted by the base.

5. In the circumstantial semantic field, Things appear as theme, Events and States appear as reference objects and 'x is a character of y' plays the role of spatial 'x is at y.' (Jackendoff 1983: 198). To exemplify this let us look at the following sentence:

(7) Ο Γιώργος λαχτάρισε τη Μαρία.
O Jórgos laxtárise ti María.
the Jórgos he.gave.a.turn the Maria
'Jórgos gave María a turn.'

In (7), Thing [MARÍA] appears as theme, Event [LAXTÁRA], the content of the base of the verb, appears as reference object, and '[MARÍA] is a character of [LAXTÁRA]' plays the role of spatial 'x is at y' (in other words, 'Jórgos has acted so that María was propelled into a frightened state' 12). As in previous cases, we have to extend the semantic field of this verb defining it as PSYCHOLOGICAL in order to properly accommodate the content of the base. 13

I have assumed that the psych-noun laxtára denotes an Event and not an Action. In this Event an animate Thing, cf. [MARÍA] in (7) is conceptualized as a kind of Actor (or lower agent) who can have control over the flow of the Action coming from another animate Thing. 14 Important in this respect is that this kind of Actor cannot be omitted in the conceptual structure. If this were the case, laxtára would denote an Action and not an Event. 15

The narrow semantic fields in 1-5 offer the basis for the licensing of the content of concrete lexical categories in concrete structural positions, e.g. in Modern Greek only the contents of Ns and As can appear as Properties in the identificational field. That is of course a language-specific preference.

On the other hand, the assertion of extended semantic fields defines situational information as an indispensable part of lexical meaning. This information is principally encoded in the base of the derivative which now has one more role to play in addition to denoting an argument in the conceptual structure. 16


2 Functions and formation rules in the spatial field

In the previous section we have seen the minimal units which compose conceptual structures, i.e. a set of conceptual constituents. According to the TRH, different semantic fields are related by means of a set of event-, state-, and place-functions (conceptual primitives) which are principally used for the description of notions of place and location. Therefore, we must first see how these functions operate on conceptual constituents in the spatial field in order to gain an overview of the processes in all fields. We will concentrate on the Event structures of -ízo derivatives mainly using the definitions made by Jackendoff (1983, 1990).

A function uses given information from a conceptual constituent and produces a result i.e. another conceptual constituent according to a formation rule. For example, a formation rule 17 for Path is:

(8) Path → PathTO[THING/PLACE]

Path function TO produces the meaning that an object (i.e. theme) moves to another object (i.e. the reference object). The formation rule in (8) says that TO operates on a Thing or Place (enclosed in brackets) in order to produce a Path (see the subscript on the left of the function). For example, in order to describe the Path constituent in the conceptual structure of the verb derivative alatízo, the TO function must be used operating on a reference object such as [FAÍ] '[MEAL].' In this way, the Thing/theme [ALÁTI] '[SALT]' (see content of the verb base), can be thought of as an entity traversing the produced Path. Therefore, the Path conceptual constituent of a sentence like (9) is decomposed as in (10).

(9) Ο μάγειρας αλατίζει το φαΐ.
O májiras alatízi to faí.
the cook he.salts the meal
(10) PathTO[FAÍ]

As the main Event function, GO produces the meaning that something is happening. It takes two arguments: the first argument is the Thing in motion, i.e. the theme and the second argument is the Path that the theme traverses on. In other words, GO maps both arguments (Thing/theme and Path) into an Event. A formation rule for Event which includes the rule in (10) is the rule in (11).

(11) Event → EventGO([THING], [PathTO[THING/PLACE]])

Not taking the agent into account, the Event constituent of sentence (9) is decomposed as follows:

(12) EventGO([ALÁTI], [PathTO[FAÍ]])

Another formation rule for Path is given in (13).

(13) Path → PathFROM [THING/PLACE]

Path function FROM produces the meaning that an object (i.e. theme) moves from another object (i.e. the reference object). The rule in (13) says that FROM operates on a Thing or Place in order to produce a Path. The conceptual structure of a verb like axnízo has to contain this function that operates on a reference object like [KATSARÓLA] '[KETTLE]' in order to produce the Path that traverses the Thing/theme [AXNÓS] '[STEAM],' represented by the verb base, in the course of its motion. Therefore, the Path constituent of a sentence like (14) is decomposed as in (15).

(14) Η κατσαρόλα αχνίζει.
I katsaróla axnízi.
the kettle it.steams
'The kettle steams.'
(15) PathFROM [KATSARÓLA]

The conceptual structure in (16) describes the whole Event contained in sentence (14) by means of the function GO.

(16) EventGO([AXNÓS], [PathFROM [KATSARÓLA]])

The meaning that an object (i.e. theme) moves through another object (i.e. a reference object) is produced by the function VIA. The formation rule in (17) says that VIA operates on a Thing or Place in order to produce a Path. That means that in order to describe the relevant Path in sentence (18), the VIA function must operate on a reference object like [PISTÓLI] '[PISTOL],' represented by the base of the verb pistolízo, producing the Path which traverses an implied Thing/theme like [SFÉRA] '[BULLET]' in the course of its motion. Therefore, the Path constituent of (18) is decomposed as in (19).

(17) Path → PathVIA[THING/PLACE]
(18) Ο σκοπευτής πιστολίζει ένα μπουκάλι.
O skopeftís pistolízi éna bukáli.
the shooter he.shoots one bottle
'The shooter shoots a bottle.'
(19) Path → PathVIA [PISTÓLI]

Similarly, in order to produce the Event reading contained in (18), we have to use the function GO. This time the conceptual structure which describes the main thematic configuration has a non-specified Thing as its theme and the Path constituent which describes details of this motion is subordinated as a modifier. (20) is the conceptual structure of (18), without involving the agent yet. 18

(20) EventGO([Thing-non specified-], [PathTO[ThingBUKÁLI]])
PathVIA [ThingPISTÓLI]

The Path and Event formation rules seen so far do not explain how an agent can be incorporated into the conceptual structures of sentences (9) and (18). This is made by a formation rule described in (21) which uses the function CAUSE in order to map a Thing (the agent) and an Event into another Event.

(21) Event → EventCAUSE([THING], [EVENT])

(22) and (23) contain sentences (9) and (18) together with their complete conceptual structures. Indexing is used to describe the correspondence between syntactic and conceptual constituents (i is used for the "external" argument, i.e. the subject, and j is used for the object).

(22) O μάγειρας αλατίζει το φαΐ.
O májiras alatízi to faí.
the cook he.salts the meal
'The cook salts the meal.'
[S [NP O májiras]i [VP alatízi [NP to faí]j]]
EventCAUSE([ThingMÁJIRAS]i, [EventGO([ALÁTI], [PathTO[FAÍ]j])])

(23) Ο σκοπευτής πιστολίζει το μπουκάλι.
O skopeftís pistolízi to bukáli.
the shooter he.shoots.with.a.pistol the bottle
'The shooter shoots the bottle (with a pistol).'
[S[NPO skopeftís]i [VPpistolízi [NPto bukáli]j]] 19
EventCAUSE([ThingSKOPEFTÍS]i, [EventGO([Thing-non specified-], [PathTO[ThingBUKÁLI]j])]) PathVIA[ThingPISTÓLI]

In this section we have seen that in the spatial field, the conceptual structures of -ízo derivatives related to Events involve the following formation rules:

(24) a. Path PathTO[THING/PLACE]
b. Path PathFROM[THING/PLACE]
c. Path PathVIA[THING/PLACE]
d. Event EventGO([THING], [PathTO[THING/PLACE]])
e. Event EventCAUSE([THING], [EVENT])

These rules must be extended in order to produce the conceptual structures of -ízo derivatives appearing in the other fields, e.g. adding a [PROPERTY] as first argument of GO in the identificational field (see (31a)), or an [EVENT] as argument of TO in the circumstantial field. A complete list of the conceptual structures produced is given in section 6 under (45).


3 Argument Fusion

We have so far accepted that the base of a derivative can represent an incorporated argument, e.g. the contents of the bases aláti and axnós are theme arguments in the conceptual structures of alatízo and axnízo, respectively. In these two verbs there is no conflict in the matching of conceptual and syntactic constituents: the incorporated argument simply received an additional role that was relevant in the conceptual structure (but not in the syntax, see section 2). However, there can be special mappings between conceptual and syntactic constituents, cf. the following sentence:

(25) Η Μαρία κέρδισε ένα αυτοκίνητο.
I María kérdise éna aftokínito.
the María she.won one car
'María won a car.'

As regards to the conceptual structure of (25), [MARÍA] is the goal and the base of the derivative kerdhízo, i.e. kérdhos, represents the theme [KÉRDHOS].

However, what happens if someone tries to integrate this information coming from the conceptual structure and the information coming from the syntax, i.e. that kerdhízo is a predicate with an internal argument (object)?

The syntactic and conceptual structure of sentence (25) is given in (26).

(26) a. Syntactic structure
[S[NPI María]i [VPkérdhíse [NPéna aftokínito]j]]
b. Conceptual structure
EventGO([KÉRDHOS]j, [PathTO[ThingMARÍA]i])

Index j indicates that the internal argument of the verb in the syntax and the incorporated argument of the verb in the conceptual structure correspond to each other. In order to integrate the information coming from the NP éna aftokínito in the conceptual structure of (26b) we cannot simply delete the information contained in the incorporated argument. This strategy would make kerdhízo a synonym of apoktó 'obtain.' One has ultimately to infer that María obtained a car and that this car was simultaneously a gain. In other words, éna aftokínito must have properties of a gain in order to be the object of the verb kerdhízo. This latter requirement leads to the conclusion that incorporated arguments can appear as selectional restrictions in the syntax (see Jackendoff 1990: 50ff).

Therefore, there must be a rule which computes the information coming from the incorporated argument in the conceptual structure and the internal argument in the argument structure/syntax. Jackendoff proposes the following rule: 20

(27) Argument Fusion
To form the conceptual structure for a syntactic phrase XP headed by a lexical item H:
a. Into each indexed constituent in H's LCS, 21 fuse the conceptual structure of that phrase YP that satisfies the co-indexed position in H's subcategorization feature.
b. If H is a verb, fuse the conceptual structure of the subject into the constituent indexed i in H's LCS.
(Jackendoff, Semantic Structures 1990: 53)

The rule under (27a) suggests that in the case of (25), in order to form the conceptual structure for the VP kérdhise éna aftokínito which is headed by the V kerdhízo, one has to fuse the conceptual structure of the NP éna aftokínito that satisfies the co-indexed position in V's subcategorization feature into the indexed constituent in V's LCS, i.e. [KÉRDHOS] (see the structures in (26)).

On the other hand, the rule under (27b) is required for the interpretation of sentences like (28).

(28) Ο Μαρτσέλο ντελαλίζει τα νέα.
O Marcello delalízi ta néa.
the Marcello he.announces.as.a.town.crier the news
'Marcello announces the news (as a town crier).'

The corresponding syntactic and conceptual structures of (28) are given in (29).

(29) a. Syntactic structure
[S[NPO Marcello]i [VPdelalízi [NPta néa]j]]
b. Conceptual structure
EventCAUSE([ThingDELÁLIS]i), [GO([ThingTA NÉA]j, [PathTO([Thing   ])])]) 22

In (29) index i indicates that the external syntactic argument o Marcello and the incorporated argument DELÁLIS in the conceptual structure correspond to each other. In order to integrate the information coming from the NP o Marcello into the conceptual structure, we cannot simply substitute the information DELÁLIS 'town crier' represented by the incorporated argument. In the best case, namely if the properties of the subject could be inferred, this would make delalízo a contextually dependent verb. As in the case of (25), the incorporated argument functions as a selectional restriction for the external argument, i.e. Marcello must have essential properties of a town crier or be a town crier himself. The rule under (27b) suggests that in order to form the conceptual structure for the V delalízo, one has to fuse the conceptual structure of the subject NP o Marcello into the constituent indexed i in V's LCS, i.e. [DELÁLIS] (see (29)).

Furthermore, the solving of reference issues by means of Argument Fusion also suggests that this rule plays an important role in the derivation process and the right interpretation of sentences containing a verb derivative. In section 1.1, I mentioned that a linguistic marking, indicating that the conceptual content of the base of a verb derivative is not referential, is the existence of a phrase in the syntax with the same indexing. As has been shown, the rule of Argument Fusion merges the content of the base and that of the co-indexed syntactic phrase, so that reference is established after the operation of the rule.


4 Ambiguous structures

So far I have presented the main formation rules generating the conceptual structure of the majority of the Event -ízo derivatives. In order to get a complete picture of the formation rules, we first have to discuss a case which Plag (1998, see 1999 as well) has pointed out concerning the semantics of English -ize derivatives.

Plag's analysis concerns 284 -ize derivatives which all are 20th century neologisms. The ambiguous conceptual structure in (30) summarizes his discussion.

(30) LCS of -ize verbs (generalized) (Plag 1998: 234)
[[   ]BASE -ize]V
{ NPi ___ NPTheme, NPTheme ___ , NPi ___ }
CAUSE ([      ]i, [GO ([Property,Thing      ]Theme/Base; [TO [Property,Thing      ]Base/Theme])]),
whereby the line contained in { } defines the syntactic environments involved. The line under CAUSE indicates the optionality of the agent.

The restricted semantic pattern in (30) can be accounted for by the following facts:

-ize was introduced in English in the 13th century following the structure of French and Latin words. From that time on -ize is almost entirely used to derive verbs from Romance vocabulary. In addition, English speakers respect this preference for the base when they produce neologisms although they may know nothing about its origin (see http://www.ling.upenn.edu/courses/Fall_1998/ling001/morphology2.html, accessed June 6, 2007). Consequently, -ize derivatives are connected to a refined style of speech which for the most part involves abstract scientific and journalistic uses. 23

On the other hand, the continuous presence of Modern Greek -ízo from ancient times up to now is manifested in a variety of patterns: -ízo derivatives with a monomorphemic base relate in their majority to casual activities involving various thematic relations, especially in the spatial semantic field (cf. alatízo, axnízo and other MG formations), and they are not restricted to a particular base or style preference, i.e. verbs with bases of various origins can be produced connected to different styles (see the Main subclass inside alternation classes in Charitonidis 2005: 87-130). But let us now see how the pattern in (30) is applied to -ízo derivation.

In (31), the first argument of GO (theme) can be a Property or a Thing which is transferred onto another Property or Thing. What is special here is that "it is either the referent of the base that is transferred to the referent of the object or the other way round" (Plag 1998: 224). To make this clear let us look at the two readings of a MG sentence which suggest this pattern:

(31) Ο μηχανικός μαγνητίζει το υλικό.
O mixanikós magnitízi to ilikó.
the engineer he.magnetizes the material
'The engineer magnetizes the material.'
a. CAUSE([ThingMIXANIKÓS], [GO([PropertyMAGNITIKÓS], [PathTO[ThingILIKÓ]])])
'The engineer induces magnetic properties in the material.'
b. CAUSE([ThingMIXANIKÓS], [GO([ThingILIKÓ], [PathTO[ThingMAGNÍTIS]])])
'The engineer converts the material into a magnet.'

Magnitízo is a neologism/translation loan created on the pattern of French magnétiser (DCMG) and mainly a scientific term (cf. the discussion about the English -ize neologisms above). The lexical category of the base cannot be unequivocally defined. According to the two readings in (31) it can be both A magnitikós 'magnetic' (31a) and N magnítis 'magnet' (31b).

The possibility of a Property appearing as theme is to be thought of as an extension of Jackendoff's TRH: in the identificational field only do Things occupy this position (see section 2). The ambiguous pattern in (31) can be explained if we look at the conceptual category of the base: it can either be a Thing/Type or a Property, i.e. conceptual categories which are closely related. 24

Similar verbs are kanonízo and pseftízo.

Let us now consider other ambiguous patterns and their explanation.

The verb aerízo has the following structure:

(32) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingAÉRAS], [PathTO[Thing       ]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[Thing AÉRAS]])])

Sentence (33) can be interpreted in two ways: either Jórgos produces the effect that aéras 'air' comes to the clothes, e.g. opening a door (see (33a)), or he brings the clothes to aéras where under aéras is rather meant a place (see (33b)). In both cases the Event takes place in the spatial field. The ambiguity seems to be due to a metonymy mechanism where the contained Thing can be thought as the container.

(33) Ο Γιώργος αερίζει τα ρούχα.
O Jórgos aerízi ta rúxa.
the Jórgos he.airs the clothes
'Jórgos airs the clothes.'
a. CAUSE([ThingJÓRGOS], [GO([ThingAÉRAS], [PathTO[ThingRÚXA]])])
b. CAUSE([ThingJÓRGOS], [GO([ThingRÚXA], [PathTO[ThingAÉRAS]])])

Akonízo is a slightly different case. Its structure is given in (34).

(34) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingAKÓNI], [PathTO[Thing       ]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[ThingAKÓNI]])])

Sentence (35) means that either Jánis moves a knife to a fixed grindstone/whet-stone (Gr. akóni the related base of the derivative), or that Jánis moves a (mechanic) grindstone/whetstone to a fixed knife (see (35a) and (35b), respectively). As in (33), both Events are in the spatial field and the conceptual categories in the theme and goal positions are the same, i.e. Things. In addition, the presence of the agent in (35) is obligatory, as opposed to (33). The ambiguity is due to real-world factors exclusively.

(35) Ο Γιάννης ακονίζει το μαχαίρι.
O Jánis akonízi to maxéri.
the Jánis he.grinds/he.whets the knife
'Jánis grinds/whets the knife.'
a. CAUSE([ThingJÁNIS], [GO([ThingAKÓNI], [PathTO[ThingMAXÉRI]])])
b. CAUSE([ThingJÁNIS], [GO([ThingMAXÉRI], [PathTO[ThingAKÓNI]])])

Similar verbs are plevrízo1, plevrízo2 and troxízo.

The structure of the derivative plimirízo is given in (36).

(36) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingPLIMÍRA], [PathTO[Thing       ]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[Thing/TypePLIMÍRA]])])

In structure (36a) the base N plimíra has the meaning 'large amount of water' and in structure (36b) the meaning 'flood,' 'overflow.' These structures relate to the spatial and identificational field, respectively. The ambiguous structure is due to the fact that the base N is principally related to two different conceptualizations of the end state of the Event, i.e. that some place is covered with large amounts of water. On the other hand, these two options can be inferred in relation to the Thing involved in the two Events, cf. [IPÓJIO] in (37a) and [POTÁMI] in (37b).

(37) a. Το υπόγειο πλημμύρισε.
To ipójio plimírise.
the basement it.flooded
'The basement was flooded.'
GO([ThingPLIMÍRA], [PathTO[ThingIPÓJIO]])
b. Το ποτάμι πλημμύρισε.
To potámi plimírise
the river it.overflowed
'The river overflowed its banks.'
GO([ThingPOTÁMI], [PathTO[Thing/TypePLIMÍRA]])

The verb asfalízo1 has the following structure:

(38) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[PropertyASFALÉS]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingASFÁLIA], [PathTO[Thing      ]])])

A asfalés 'secure' and N asfália 'lock' can appear as bases of the derivative, cf. (38a) and (38b), respectively. The former reading denotes that someone secures something in the identificational field and the latter reading denotes that someone attaches a Thing like [ASFÁLIA] '[LOCK]' to another Thing in the spatial field. (39) can have both readings. Its ambiguity seems to be due to a conceptual mechanism which relates a goal/Property to a theme/Thing.

(39) Ο γέροντας ασφαλίζει το υπόγειο.
O jérodas asfalízi to ipójio.
the old.man he.secures/he.locks the cellar
'The old man secures/locks the cellar.'
a. CAUSE([ThingJÉRODAS], [GO([ThingIPÓJIO], [PathTO[PropertyASFALÉS]])])
b. CAUSE([ThingJÉRODAS],[GO([ThingASFÁLIA], [PathTO[ThingIPÓJIO]])])

A slightly different case is onidhízo which has the following structure:

(40) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[EventÓNIDHOS]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingÓNIDHOS], [PathTO[Thing    ]])])

Base N ónidhos appears in (40a) with the meaning 'disgrace' and in (40b) with the meaning 'blame.' The former reading denotes that someone brings someone or something in disgrace in the circumstantial field and the second reading denotes that someone expresses a blame against someone or something in the spatial field. (41) can have both readings.

(41) Η αντιπολίτευση ονειδίζει τον πρωθυπουργό.
I adipolítefsi onidhízi ton prothipurgó.
the opposition he.disgraces/he.blames the prime-minister
'The opposition disgraces/blames the prime-minister.'
a. CAUSE([ThingADIPOLÍTEFSI], [GO([ThingPROTHIPURGÓS], [PathTO[EventÓNIDHOS]])])
b. CAUSE([ThingADIPOLÍTEFSI], [GO([ThingÓNIDHOS], [PathTO[ThingPROTHIPURGÓS]])])

In both readings, the main extended semantic field is CONFLICT. The ambiguity seems to come from the fact that in structure (41b) the semantic field VERBAL is added, which favours a spatial interpretation of the Event. 25

Similar verbs are midhenízo2 and kakízo.

Real-world factors define the ambiguity of the verb orkízo. Its base órkos can mean 'oath' or 'swearing,' cf. the following structure:

(42) a. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([ThingÓRKOS], [PathTO[Thing       ]])])
b. CAUSE([Thing      ], [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[EventÓRKOS]])])

(43) can be interpreted in two ways: either o prítanis addresses an oath to the graduates (reading (43a)) or he brings the graduates to the Event of swearing to something (reading (43b)). In the first case the Event takes place in the spatial field and in the second case in the circumstantial field. The ambiguity seems to come from the fact that the focus on the initial or final state of the whole Event suggests the interpretation of the content of the base of orkízo as Thing or Event, respectively: The one focus point consists of someone addressing an oath to another person at the beginning of the Event (reading (43a)) and the other of the addressee swearing to something at the end of this Event (reading (43b)).

(43) Ο πρύτανης ορκίζει τους αποφοίτους.
O prítanis orkízi tus apofítus.
the rector he.puts.under.oath the graduates
'The rector puts the graduates under oath.'
a. CAUSE([ThingPRÍTANIS], [GO([ThingÓRKOS], [PathTO[ThingAPÓFITI]])])
b. CAUSE([ThingPRÍTANIS], [GO([ThingAPÓFITI], [PathTO[EventÓRKOS]])])

So far we have examined ambiguity cases, in which the conceptual structures always contained a Path TO function. The last case involves the shift of the Path function which results in different readings, cf. the following two examples and their corresponding LCSs.

(44) a.
Ο καταστηματάρχης δειγματίζει τα προϊόντα στη βιτρίνα.
O katastimatárxis dhigmatízi ta proióda sti vitrína.
the shopkeeper he.samples the products in-the shop.window
'The shopkeeper puts the products as samples in the shop window.'
[S[NPO katastimatárxis]i [VPdhigmatízi [NPta proióda]j 26[PP se [NP ti vitrína]k]]]
CAUSE([ThingKATASTIMATÁRXIS]i, [GO([ThingDHÍGMA]j, [PathTO[ThingVITRÍNA]k])])
b. Ο γεωπόνος δειγματίζει το βαμβάκι.
O jeopónos dhigmatízi to vamváki.
the agronomist he.samples the cotton-plant
'The agronomist takes a sample from the cotton-plant.'
CAUSE([ThingJEOPÓNOS], [GO([ThingDHÍGMA], [PathFROM[ThingVAMVÁKI]])])

In both sentences, the base N dhígma of the verb dhigmatízo denotes a theme. The different readings are related to the fact that the LCS of (44a) contains a Path TO function and the LCS of (44b) contains a Path FROM function.

To summarize: In relation to -ízo derivatives, the following elements play an important conceptual role:

a. The conceptual (ontological) category of the base, cf. magnitízo, asfalízo.
b. The narrow semantic field, cf. plimirízo, asfalízo.
c. The extended semantic field, cf. onidhízo.
d. Metonymy mechanisms, cf. aerízo.
e. Real-world factors, cf. akonízo.
f. Situational factors related to different Path functions in the conceptual structure, cf. dhigmatízo.

There can be no evaluation of these factors, since the attested ambiguity phenomena must be tested on a larger corpus of data and with different suffixes in order to be validated. The corresponding conceptual structures are marginal, i.e. the only ones which appeared in the analysis. The main point to be made here is that the used conceptual model covers all these factors and sufficiently explains the ambiguities.


5 Conceptual structures in -ízo derivation (overview)

In the previous section, I completed the presentation of the basic LCSs involved in the Event -ízo derivatives. The list in (45) gives an overview of the discussion so far. It refers to the syntactic frame NPi ___ NP and a verb in the causative active form. 'IA' stands for the incorporated argument. The line under CAUSE indicates that the agent can be absent in the b alternation variant.

(45) LCS1: CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing-IA-], [PathTO[Thing      ]])])
LCS2: CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[Thing,Property,Event-IA-]])])
LCS3: a. CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing,Property-IA-], [PathTO[Thing      ]])]) or
b. CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[Thing,Property,Event-IA-]])])
LCS4: CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing-IA-], [FROM[Thing      ]])])
LCS5: CAUSE([Thing      ]i, [GO([Thing      ], [PathTO[Thing      ]])])
VIA[Thing-IA-]
LCS6: CAUSE([Thing-IA-]i), [GO([Thing     ] j, [PathTO[Thing      ]k])])
Syntactic frame: NPi ___ NPj {PPk}

Sentences (46)-(52) exemplify the structures in (45). Some examples have already been used in the previous sections and are repeated here. All verbs are in the causative active form.

(46) LCS1 27
O μάγειρας αλατίζει το φαγητό.
O májiras alatízi to fajitó. (base: N aláti 'salt')
the cook he.salts the meal
'The cook salts the meal.'
CAUSE([ThingMÁJIRAS], [GO([ThingALÁTI], [PathTO[ThingFAJITÓ]])])
(47) LCS2
Η γυναίκα καθαρίζει το πουκάμισο.
I jinéka katharízi to pukámiso. (base: A katharós A 'clean')
the woman he.cleans the shirt
'The woman cleans the shirt.'
CAUSE([ThingJINÉKA], [GO([ThingPUKÁMISO], [PathTO[PropertyKATHARÓ]])])
(48) LCS3a
Ο μηχανικός μαγνητίζει το υλικό.
O mixanikós magnitízi to ilikó. (base: A magnitikós 'magnetic')
the engineer he.magnetizes the material
'The engineer magnetizes the material.' (he induces magnetic properties in the material)
CAUSE([ThingMIXANIKÓS], [GO([PropertyMAGNITIKÓS], [PathTO[ThingILIKÓ]])])
(49) LCS3b
Ο μηχανικός μαγνητίζει το υλικό.
O mixanikós magnitízi to ilikó. (base: N magnítis 'magnet')
the engineer he.magnetizes the material
'The engineer magnetizes the material.' (he converts the material into a magnet)
CAUSE([ThingMIXANIKÓS], [GO([ThingILIKÓ], [PathTO[ThingMAGNÍTIS]])])
(50) LCS4
Ο Γιώργος καπνίζει ένα τσιγάρο.
O Jórgos kapnízi éna tsigáro (base: N kapnós 'smoke')
the Jórgos he.smokes one cigarette
'Jórgos smokes a cigarette.'
CAUSE([ThingJÓRGOS], [GO([ThingKAPNÓS], [FROM[ThingTSIGÁRO]])])
(51) LCS5
Ο σκοπευτής πιστολίζει ένα μπουκάλι.
O skopeftís pistolízi éna bukáli. (base: N pistóli 'pistol')
the shot he.shoots one bottle
'The shot shoots a bottle (with a pistol).'
CAUSE([ThingSKOPEFTÍS], [GO([Thing-non specified-], [PathTO[ThingBUKÁLI]])])
VIA[ThingPISTÓLI]
(52) LCS6
Ο Μαρτσέλο ντελαλίζει τα νέα στην πόλη.
O Marcello delalízi ta néa stin póli. (base: N delális 'town crier')
the Marcello he.announces.as.a.town.crier the news in-the town
'Marcello announces the news in the town (as a town crier).'
CAUSE([ThingDELÁLIS]), [GO([ThingNÉA], [PathTO[ThingPÓLI]])])

Two parameters are crucial for the differentiation of the structures in (45), i.e. the position of the content of the incorporated argument in each conceptual structure and the Path function used.

Furthermore, in the LCSs in (45), the main thematic Event appears in a minimal structure. In this way, structural similarities or differences between lexical units are pointed out more strikingly. The most important consequence of such an approach is that extended semantic fields are needed in order to compensate the reduction of the conceptual structures. Let us look at an example:

Jackendoff (1990: 142-145) defines the instrument role structurally by means of the action tier, 28 e.g. the conceptual structure of (53) should contain the two action tiers in (54), which denote that the actor acts on the instrument and the instrument acts on the patient, respectively.

(53) Η γριά ραβδίζει τα κλαδιά.
I griá ravdhízi ta kladhiá.
the old.woman she.hits.with.a.stick the twigs
'The old woman hits the twigs with a stick.'
(54) a. AFFˉ([GRIÁ], [RAVDHÍ])
b. AFFˉ([RAVDHÍ], [KLADHIÁ])

If we extend the spatial semantic field to the situational field INSTRUMENT, there is no need for the structural definition in (54). LCS1 must be only used in order to define that the incorporated argument [RAVDHÍ] '[STICK]' moves to another entity, leaving the flow of the action described in (54a) to be inferred from the INSTRUMENT field. On top of this, the use of the same extended field makes the description of the opposite case, in which the instrument is the goal of the action, simpler, cf. (55).

(55) Η εργάτρια μασουρίζει το νήμα.
I ergátria masurízi to níma.
the factory-girl she.winds.onto.a.reel the thread
'The factory-girl winds the thread onto a reel.'

(55) denotes a situation in which an agent uses both hands. In the one hand there is a thread and in the other a reel. If we follow the action tier solution like that in (54), we should have to invent a structure containing two action pairs, i.e. the pairs in (56) and (57), in order to describe two simultaneous movements.

(56) a. AFFˉ([ERGÁTRIA], [MASÚRI])
b. AFFˉ([MASÚRI], [NÍMA])
(57) a. AFFˉ([ERGÁTRIA], [NÍMA])
b. AFFˉ([NÍMA], [MASÚRI])

LCS2 gives a more natural solution: it describes that the theme [NÍMA] comes to the incorporated argument [MASÚRI], which is the main thematic Event. As in (53), the field INSTRUMENT takes over details of the action which are not visible in syntax. 29

In a similar way, the structural complexity and plurality of functions in verbs of touching, pure contact, attachment, and others (see Jackendoff 1990) are reduced by means of extended (= situational) semantic fields like CONTACT, ATTACHMENT, etc., which now mark the conceptual arguments without further decomposition. 30

There is thus a counter-balancing of conceptual structures and semantic/situational fields: the richer the fields the poorer the structures and the other way around.

The collapsing of the conceptual categories Thing and Place into a single Thing category as argument of the functions TO and FROM, as well as the use of TO and FROM as general direction functions, are two further structural reductions related to the minimal conceptual structure approach adopted here, cf. (52) where [PÓLI] is, strictly speaking, a Place and not a Thing and (46) where [ALÁTI] comes on the meal suggesting the function ON instead of TO in the Path constituent. As mentioned above, the aim of this tactic is to isolate the core thematic Event by focusing on essential similarities or differences between lexical items.

In conclusion, the set of conceptual structures appearing in -ízo derivation show that there is no restricted pattern in this domain, in that the content of the derivation base can assume a variety of semantic roles. Therefore, I cannot give any justice to the claim that morphological productivity is always based on a semantically restricted and homogeneous pattern connected with a limited range of choices which a native speaker makes when producing new words (cf. van Marle 1988, Plag 1998, 1999). 31


6 Conclusion

By taking for granted that the derivational process is based on overt morphological processes, the content of the derivation base receives a prominent status: the derivation base points to a semantic/situational field and this field should not be ignored or decomposed into a detailed conceptual structure. By means of this strategy, many ambiguities in the meaning of the -ízo derivatives can be explained (see section 5).

Further significant points made in this paper were the co-operation of narrow and extended semantic fields (the latter always related to the situational content of the derivation base - see section 2) and the disconnection of productivity from a limited and homogenous semantic pattern (see section 6).

It remains to be seen how this approach can be further developed through its application to Greek derivatives with various suffixes or other affixed elements.


Abbreviations

A Adjective
AF Argument Fusion
AFF- Negative Affect
AFF+ Positive Affect
DCMG Dictionary of Common Modern Greek (Leksikó tis Kinís Neoelinikís)
H Head
IA Incorporated Argument
LCS Lexical Conceptual Structure
LL Lexicon of Linguistics ( http://www2.let.uu.nl/UiL-OTS/Lexicon/, accessed June 6, 2007)
MG Modern Greek
N Noun
NP Noun Phrase
TRH Thematic Relations Hypothesis
VtV Verb to Verb (morphological subclass)

Notes

* This paper is a revised and extended version of Charitonidis (2005: 43-62). back

1 These verbs are called 'synchronically related verbs' in Charitonidis (2005). I have chosen this suffix because of the variety of the bases to which it is attached (i.e. N, A, V, ADV). This is universally more promising since generalizations across categories can be made, especially in terms of the conceptual model at hand. back

2 The output list of the 3506 verbs was taken by entering the end string -ίζω in the search box at http://www.komvos.edu.gr:8080/dictionaries/dictOnLine/DictOnLineRev.htm, accessed June 6, 2007. back

3 For a complete view of the exclusion criteria see Charitonidis (2005: 35-37). back

4 This selection of syntactic frames has a concrete motivation: it is connected to the assignment of a derivative to a set of alternations (see note 9). back

5 The definition of these conceptual constituents is made in Jackendoff (1983: 41-56). back

6 With the exception of whole Events or States, conceptual arguments are enclosed in brackets and indicated with capital letters. back

7 This hypothesis is a version of Gruber's hypothesis (1965). back

8 Situational fields represent a complex of features. I did not attempt to integrate them into the formalism, since they rather relate to the alternations component and the action frames in which the derivatives appear (see note 9). The starting point for their differentiation is the content of the base. For example, from the two main semantic elements which compose the meaning of the verb stubízo 'pestle', i.e. INSTRUMENT & CONTACT BY IMPACT, the dominant semantic field is INSTRUMENT, since it immediately represents the content of the base stúbos. We can call the field CONTACT BY IMPACT, an accompanying semantic feature/field, since it figures only after the association of the base with a conceptual structure, i.e. a conceptual structure which contains a theme moving to a reference object, cf. the following sentence with its conceptual structure (LCS1):

(i) Η Μαρία στουμπίζει τα αμύγδαλα.
O María stubízei ta amígdhala.
the María she.pestles the almonds
'María pestles the almonds.'
CAUSE([MARÍA], [GO([STÚBOS], [PathTO[AMÍGDALA]])])

The clear-cut distinction between a dominant semantic field and an accompanying semantic field/feature is not always obvious, cf. the derivative ramfízo, whose base rámfos denotes a BODY PART and an INSTRUMENT or xastukízo, whose base xastúki only implies (but does not denote) a BODY PART or an INSTRUMENT. Cases like these are decided again according to the content of the base: the dominant semantic fields are BODY PART in ramfízo and CONTACT BY IMPACT WITH BODY PART in xastukízo since their bases rámfos and xastúki denote a Thing or Action, respectively.
A more difficult case is represented by verbs like afionízo, whose base afióni can be thought of to refer to the fields FOOD/DRINK, SUBSTANCE, or PSYCHOLOGICAL. Since afióni refers to an object, the FOOD/DRINK or SUBSTANCE option seems more adequate. But in a situational approach the regarding of this field as dominant can only partially account for the semantics of the derivative. In this context, a principled solution cannot be offered. Cases like this are accounted for by means of complex semantic fields, e.g. FOOD/DRINK & SUBSTANCE & PSYCHOLOGICAL for afionízo (whereby the field PSYCHOLOGICAL may be inferred from the other fields).
Let us try to summarize the process of accessing the semantic fields of -ízo derivatives:
(a) The content of the base of the derivative sets the frame of a semantic field, (b) there is a dominant field related to the denotatum of the base of the derivative and an accompanying field or feature related to its whole conceptual structure, and (c) if the content of the base fails to represent the Event denoted by the derivative, then the content of the whole situation can be represented by a complex of semantic fields/features (the argumentation in this note is adopted from Charitonidis 2005: 80f). back

9 In Charitonidis (2005) nine alternations were asserted, i.e. 1a/b: Active Causative / Active Auto, 2a/b: Active Causative / Passive Auto, 3a/b: Active Causative / Active Reflexive, 4a/b: Active Causative / Passive Reflexive, 5a/b: Active Causative / Active Reciprocal, 6a/b: Active Causative / Passive Reciprocal, 7a/b: Active Causative / Active Control, 8a/b: Active Causative / Passive Control, and 9: Passive Participle (with only one member). These alternations were defined according to discussions of relevant phenomena in Levin (1993) and Smith (1978). The final definition of the alternations was made according to the morphological system of the Modern Greek verb, in which active or non-active morphology can sometimes be used indifferently, cf. the verb forms skorpízo (active) and skorpístika (nonactive) with the same meaning (= "I was scattered"–alternations 1b and 2b, respectively). The basis of the analysis was ultimately the conceptual structures and functions introduced by Jackendoff (1983, 1990), further developed by the author.
In the following, I describe the semantics of these alternations in brief:
The causative variant (indicated with a above) involves an agent as instigator of an Event. The auto variant (see 1b and 2b) refers to Events where an agent may have initiated a process, but this process is conceptualized independently of him. The reflexive variant (see 3b and 4b) refers to an Event where the goal of the control action of an agent is himself or a part of himself. The reciprocal variant (see 5b and 6b) refers to Events in which each agent is the goal of the action of the other agent. In the control variant (see 7b and 8b), the agent is present during the whole Event, esp. he defines beginning, end, and perhaps even particular stages of the Event. The passive participle (alternation 9) denotes an established end state (see Charitonidis 2005: 7-24 for details).
To give an example of the action frames defined by (some of) these alternations, see how the senses of the verb kapnízo are differentiated in the following table:

kapnízo
Verbs Senses Alternation Classes Semantic Fields Conceptual Structures
kapnízo1 'smoke',
'give off smoke'
1*a/b_*9
(No alternations)
EMISSION/
ENDOGENOUS PRODUCT
LCS4
kapnízo2 'smoke', 'cure' 2a/b_8a/b_9 COVERING LCS1
kapnízo3 'smoke', 'puff' 8a/b_9 EMISSION/
ENDOGENOUS PRODUCT
LCS4

1*a/b_*9: *Causative Active/Auto Active_*Passive Participle
2a/b_8a/b_9: Causative Active/Auto Passive_Causative Active/Control Passive_Passive Participle
8a/b_9: Causative Active/Control Passive_Passive Participle
As becomes apparent from this table, three components co-operate, i.e. conceptual structures, alternation classes, and semantic fields, the most important component being the alternations component, which sets the action frames and ultimately differentiates the meanings (see also Charitonidis 2006). back

10 Inalienable possession is, for example, the possession of a Thing like someone's own nose (see Jackendoff 1983:191 and the relevant references there). Jackendoff relates location not only to a single reference object, because he examines verbs like give, involving the participation of more than one individual, or transaction verbs like buy, for which both the location is thought of as a transfer of Things from one individual to another, e.g. in the case of the English verb buy, the course of a Thing (theme) going from one individual to another constitutes a location as a whole. For the syntactic frames NPi __NP / NP__ and under a minimal lexical decomposition approach (see section 3.5), these structures are not relevant. back

11 As in the case of the possessive field, being an instance of a category or having a property can appear as a complex reference object, cf. the English sentences 'The coach changed from a handsome young man into a pumpkin' and 'Sally is three inches shorter than Bill' (see Jackendoff 1983: 194ff). Again, for the syntactic frames examined here (see note 10 above), these cases need not concern us. back

12 The conceptual status of this 'state' is regarded as an Event in which Maria is the main protagonist. back

13 Jackendoff (1983: 198) argues that 'syntactically, circumstantial verbs always subcategorize a subordinate clause that expresses the reference [EVENT] or [STATE].' We have shown that in the PSYCHOLOGICAL field as an extension of the circumstantial field, this is not always the case. back

14 Cf. the relevant argumentation for the psych-verbs in Charitonidis (2005: 16f). back

15 See Charitonidis (2005: 69f) for a structural definition of Actions and Events. back

16 The main issue which arises from the analysis is the inter-defining of narrow and extended semantic fields. Some more elaboration of the narrow semantic fields is needed, cf. the verb magnitízo for which the spatial field was assumed. In this case a candidate field were "TRANSFER OF ENERGY" and the like. I leave this issue for future research. back

17 A list of basic formation rules is found in Jackendoff (1990: 43). back

18 In (20), the constituent PathVIA [PISTÓLI] modifies the main constituent [PathTO[ThingBUKÁLI]]), producing a complex Path. Under the current approach, the instrument role is ascribed to the semantic field INSTRUMENT (see section 6 and note 8 of this paper for further details). In Jackendoff (1990: 142-145), the instrument role is mainly indicated by the function BY. back

19 From now on, I give the syntactic structure only for cases in which the correspondence of the conceptual to syntactic arguments needs clarification, cf. the cases of Argument Fusion in the next sections. back

20 I use a simple formulation of this rule and not its final version, which is integrated in a theory of linking (see Jackendoff 1990: 264). back

21 'LCS' stands for 'Lexical Conceptual Structure.' back

22 The empty Thing slot of the Path argument in (29b) can be filled with the content of a NP, like póli 'town,' contained in a PP, like stin póli 'in the town.' back

23 See a list of 20th century neologisms in Plag (1998: 239-241). back

24 For further justifications of this structure see Charitonidis (2005: 65-68). back

25 See Charitonidis (2005: 65-68) for the exact conceptual specification of verbal units as themes. back

26 Index j indicates that the conceptual content of the argument proióda in the syntax and the conceptual content of the argument dhígma in the LCS are to be fused. back

27 Note that this example refers to an LCS1 whereby an agent cannot be absent in the b alternation variant of the derivative. However, this is not always the case, cf. verbs like progízo2 and skonízo in Charitonidis (2005). In LCS1 under (45) I have explicitly indicated that the agent is optional, i.e. absent in the b variant. As far as the content of the derivation base occupies the theme position in both cases, the optionality of the agent in the b variant is assumed at a more general level of conceptual structure. back

28 The six presented LCSs for the -ízo verbs refer to the thematic tier, the conceptual part dealing with motion and location. Jackendoff (1990, 125ff) introduces an additional level of conceptual structure, i.e. the action tier, dealing with Actor-Patient relations. He uses the function AFF ("affect") to denote these relations.
This function has two optional arguments. The first argument is the "Actor" and the second argument is the "Patient" or the "affected entity," e.g. the action tier of (i) is (ii).

(i) Ο άγιος ακοντίζει το φίδι.
O ájios akodízi to fídhi.
'The saint hits the sneak with a javelin.'
(ii) AFF([ÁJIOS], [FÍDHI]),
where [ÁJIOS] is the Actor and [FÍDHI] is the Patient.

The AFF function is elaborated, among others, into AFF+ which indicates an Event in favour of the Patient and AFF- which indicates an Event against the Patient (as in the sentence above).
The action tier in (ii) is an example of AFF-. Sentence (iii) contains AFF+ (see iv).

(iii) Ο Γιώργος κέρδισε ένα αυτοκίνητο.
O Jórgos kérdhise éna aftokínito.
'Jórgos won a car.'
(iv) AFF+([    ], [JÓRGOS])

The Actor or the Patient slot can be empty, cf. (iv) with an empty actor slot. back

29 For further justifications of the INSTRUMENT field see Charitonidis (2005: 80-82). back

30 Cf. the treatment of kapnízo in note 9. back

31 For example, van Marle (1988) assumes that the decrease in productivity of the Dutch suffix -lijk (with the basic meaning 'having the nature of,' 'possible') is ascribed to a basic tripartite semantics of the suffix, together with other factors such as the rise of 'modal' features and metaphorical readings in the respective adjectives. An important note: the structures in (45) represent a group of basic semantic patterns attested among 182 'synchronically related' -ízo derivatives (cf. note 1). Opaque derivatives and derivatives as products of once-only-rules or metaphorical shifts were not taken into account. Given the fact that all the latter constitute a significant part of the verbs examined (101 verbs out of a total of 283), we get a much more heterogeneous set of forms–a fact which strengthens our claims. In addition, the structures in (45) were attested both in new and old derivation: as concerns the conceptual structure of the verbs in the new derivation (the verbs of this class are called 'Main verbs' in Charitonidis 2005), in a total of 50 derivatives, LCS1 was attested in 22 derivatives, LCS2 in 18 derivatives, LCS3 in five derivatives, LCS4 in two derivatives, LCS5 in one derivative, and LCS6 in two derivatives. As concerns the conceptual structure of the verbs in the old derivation, in a total of 112 derivatives, LCS1 was attested in 44 derivatives, LCS2 in 55 derivatives, LCS3 in six derivatives, LCS4 in six derivatives, LCS5 in one derivative, and LCS6 in one derivative (see Charitonidis 2005: 80-84). back


References

Anastasiádhi-Simeonídhi, Anna (2002): Adístrofo Leksikó tis Néas Elinikís ('Reverse Index of Modern Greek'). Thesaloníki.

Charitonidis, Chariton (2005): Verb Derivation in Modern Greek. Alternation Classes, Conceptual Structures, Semantic Fields. Frankfurt. (= Europäische Hochschulschriften, Reihe 21: Linguistik 284).

Jackendoff, Ray (1983): Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA.

Jackendoff, Ray (1990): Semantic Structures. Cambridge, MA.

Jackendoff, Ray (1992): "Parts and boundaries." In: Levin, B. and S. Pinker (eds.) (1992): Lexical and Conceptual Semantics, 9-45.

Plag, Ingo (1998): "The polysemy of -ize derivatives. On the role of semantics in word formation." In: Booij, Geert/van Marle, Jaap (eds.) (1998): Yearbook of Morphology 1997, 219-242. Dordrecht.

Plag, Ingo (1999): Morphological Productivity. Structural Constraints in English Derivation. Berlin.

Sasse, Hans-Jürgen (1993): "Das Nomen. Eine universale Kategorie?" Sprachtypologie und Universalienforschung (STUF) 46/3: 187-221.

van Marle, Jaap (1988): On the role of semantics in productivity change. In: Booij, Geert/van Marle, Jaap (eds.) (1988): The Yearbook of Morphology 1988, 139-154. Dordrecht.


Appendix 1: 182 synchronically related verbs in -ízo appearing inside alternation classes

adhinatízo exmalotízo kedrízo midhenízo2 plutízo1 sinexízo thorakízo
adikrízo fanatízo kerdhízo1 mistrízo podízo skonízo thrimatízo
aerízo fenakízo kimatízo molopízo pomatízo skorpízo1 tiganízo
afionízo fevgatízo kitrinízo murmurízo prasinízo1 skorpízo2 tixízo
afrízo filakízo kokinízo1 nostimízo prasinízo2 skorpízo4 tonízo1
akonízo fortízo kopanízo onidhízo prionízo skupízo1 torpilízo
alatízo fotízo koskinízo onomatízo progízo2 sofronízo travmatízo
alonízo foverízo krimatízo oplízo provlimatízo stalízo troxízo
anthízo fovízo ksilízo orízo1 psalidhízo stavlízo tsiknízo
armirízo friganízo ksinízo1 orjízo pseftízo stigma-tízo tufekízo
aromatízo frodízo ksinízo2 orkízo psifízo stiximatízo vasanízo1
arxízo fronimatízo ksirafízo ovelízo psithirízo stixízo2 vithízo
asfalízo1 furkízo kutsulízo panijirízo psonízo stolízo2 votanízo
asfalízo2 furnízo lanarízo papagalízo ravdhízo strovilízo1 vurtsízo
asprízo1 gremízo2 laxtarízo paspalízo ripízo strovilízo2 xalalízo
asprízo2 ikízo lianízo1 patsízo rithmízo1 stubízo xaramízo
asximízo ionízo(iodízo) lonxízo peanízo rokanízo1 suvlízo xastukízo
axnízo2 ipnotízo luludhízo pexnidhízo sapunízo svarnízo xeretízo1
batirízo kalafatízo madrízo pikrízo satirízo svurízo xrimatízo1
blavízo kanonízo magnitízo pipilízo sekletízo sximatízo1 xrisízo
delalízo kapnízo2 makarízo pitsilízo serjanízo sximatízo2 xromatízo
dhigmatízo kapnízo3 mastízo planízo sfaliarízo tagízo xtenízo
dhraskelízo kapsalízo mavrízo plevrízo1 sfrajízo telonízo zalízo
dhrosízo1 karpízo meremetízo plevrízo2 sfugarízo temaxízo zijízo1
dhrosízo2 katharízo merízo plimirízo silavízo termatízo1 zografízo
evnuxízo kazadízo midhenízo1 plumízo sinetízo thiafízo zorízo

Appendix 2: List of -ízo verbs discussed

Note: form and meaning of the (related) base is given in Modern Greek! '~' next to the base indicates the immediate derivative (see Verb-to-Verb (VtV) subclass in Charitonidis (2005: 33f).

Verbs in -ízo
adikrízo 'see', 'meet'
aerízo 'air'
afionízo 'give sb opium'
akodízo 'hit with a javelin'
akonízo 'grind', 'whet'
alatízo 'salt'
alonízo 'thresh'
asfalízo1 'secure', 'lock'
axnízo1 'steam', 'emit steam'
delalízo 'announce sth as a town crier'
dhigmatízo 'put a sample on show', 'take a sample'
kakízo 'disgrace', 'disapprove'
kanonízo 'regulate', 'adjust', etc.
kapnízo1 'smoke', 'give off smoke'
kapnízo2 'smoke', 'cure'
kapnízo3 'smoke', 'puff'
katharízo 'clean'
kerdhízo1 'earn'
kokinízo1 'redden', 'make sth red'
laxtarízo 'give sb a turn'
magnitízo 'magnetize'
masurízo 'wind sth on a reel'
midhenízo2 'reduce to zero' (for counter),
'give no marks at all'
(literally 'give the mark 0')
onidhízo 'disgrace', 'blame'
orkízo 'put sb on/under oath', 'swear in'
pistolízo 'shoot with a pistol', 'shoot'
plevrízo1 'anchor', 'drop/cast anchor'
plevrízo2 'come up to', 'draw/come alongside'
plimirízo 'overflow', 'flood'
prasinízo1 'make green'
progízo2 'shy' (animal), 'scare'
pseftízo 'reduce the quality of sth'
ramfízo 'peck (at)', 'pick'
ravdhízo 'beat with a stick'
skonízo 'cover with dust'
sosialízo 'have a socialistic
attitude/behaviour'
stubízo 'pestle'
termatízo1 'bring to an end'
troxízo 'whet', 'grind'
xaramízo 'waste'
xastukízo 'slap sb in the face'
zorízo 'put pressure on sb'
(Related) Base
adíkri ADV 'facing', 'vis-á-vis'
aéras N 'air'
afióni N 'opium'
akódio N 'javelin'
akóni (~akonéo) N 'grindstone', 'whetstone'
aláti N 'salt'
alóni N 'threshing floor'
asfalís A 'secure'
axnós N 'steam'
delális N 'town crier'
dhígma N 'sample'
kakós A 'bad'
kanónas N 'precept', 'rule'
kapnós N 'smoke'
kapnós N 'smoke'
kapnós N 'smoke'
katharós A 'clean'
kérdhos N 'profit', 'gain'
kókinos A 'red'
laxtára A 'fright', 'turn'
magnítis, magnitikós N, A 'magnet', 'magnetic'
masúri N 'reel'
midhén


N 'zero'
ónidhos N 'disgrace', 'blame'
órkos N 'oath', 'swearing'
pistóli N 'pistol'
plevró N 'side'
plevró N 'side'
plimíra N 'overflow', 'flood'
prásinos A 'green'
próga N 'aggressive teasing'
pséftis N 'liar'
rámfos N 'bill', 'beak'
ravdhí N 'stick'
skóni N 'dust'
sosialismós,
sosialistís
N, N 'socialism',
'socialist'
stúbos N 'pestle'
térma N 'end'
troxós N 'whetting/grinding wheel'
xarámi ADV 'in vain', 'be wasted'
xastúki N 'slap/smack in the face'
zóri N 'stress', 'force'

Appendix 3: Verb endings in Modern Greek


Adapted from Holton, David/Mackridge, Peter/Philippaki-Warburton, Irene (1997): Greek. A comprehensive grammar of the modern language. London: 116, with permission.